The Heart and Soul of Marxian Theory



Abstract

This exegetical essay puts forward the thesis that the growth of the "human-social forces of production" is the '''heart and soul''' of the Marxian theory of the causation of human-social evolution, and of human-social revolution.

That is, this essay holds that, per Marx, the human-society self-induced growth of the "human-social forces of production" is the core cause of the historically observed — as of the predicted future — changes in the "human-social relations of production", the human-social relations which mediate the self-reproduction, and the self-transformation, of human societies.

This thesis is supported, in this essay, by extensive evidence from the published writings of Karl Marx, as well as from surviving writings by Marx left unpublished during his lifetime.

Hypothesis

"The growth of the social forces of production" is the heart of the Marxian theory of the causation of human-social evolution, and of human-social revolution.

It is the core of Marx's explanation of the continual, cumulative changes within each historically-observed system of human social relations [of the transitory self-reproduction of that system of social relations].

It is also the core of Marx's explanation of the historically-observed changes that constitute the transition from each predecessor system of human social relations to its successor system of human social relations, characterized by a partial conservation of the predecessor ontology of social relations, as well as by an irruption of new, unprecedented social-relations ontology.

In Marxian theory, the growth of the human-social forces of production is also the primary project of human liberation.

Per Marx, it is already so within that human pre-history which ends with the end of the predominance of the "capital-relation" as all-subsuming social relation of production, and it is so also, and even more so, within the predicted future, next epoch, that of the social relation of production of the freely and democratically "associated producers", which Marx also calls "communist society".

This liberatory project, per Marx, cannot be a conscious, deliberate collective human project within the entire span of "human prehistory" — a prehistory which, per Marx, only ends with the emergence of humanity from its capital-value-form.

Before that emergence, this project of human liberation is part of the "cunning" of the human species' collective, or social, unconscious mind.

Specifically, under the rule of the capital-value-form, this project is not pursued, collectively, consciously as such, but only indirectly, and under other, misleading, "ideological" forms of human consciousness.

This project is pursued, essentially, only in the form of the pursuit of transitory "super-profit" opportunities by the personifications of the "capital-relation", via their effort to increase the productivity of their wage-labor inputs so as to reduce the unit cost of their commodity output, and, thereby, to (1) undercut their competitors' pricing, on equivalent output, at the same rate of profit, or (2) to meet their competitors' prices, at a higher rate of profit, or (3) some intermediate combination of the two forgoing strategy-extremes.

Upon critical, deeper analysis, this is revealed, by Marx, to be the de facto pursuit of rising rates of "relative surplus-value", though it is not such in the typical consciousness of the agents/personifications of the "capital-relation".

For individuals outside the class of capital-personification, e.g., for wagéd and salaried workers, the development of what they tend, in the present-day ideological context, to "hear" from the phrase "the productive forces" — namely, so-called "technology" — and the choice of "technology", appear to be an alien affair, an affair of capital and its engineering, etc., employees, from which the wage-working population is excluded.

Such "technology" may even appear, to 'impressionistic empiricists', in an illusory 'real subjects/real objects'-inverted manner, as an autonomous development, outside of any human-social intension or control: "technology" as the [pseudo-]subject, or [pseudo-agent, of human history.

The associated feeling of estrangement with respect to such "technology" on the part of workers is a 'psycho-ideological vulnerability' produced in them by their very 'capital-relation' experience itself.

That feeling can be exploited in the psychological/ideological class-warfare operations of a capitalist ruling faction hell-bent on "saving itself" from Marx's predicted outcome of the growth of the human-society-productive forces under the capital-relation — saving its power to despotically rule over all of global society — by engineering, first, a termination, and, thereafter, a reversal, of the historical "growth of the productive forces", together with all of the catastrophic, 'multi-genocidal', tendentially '''humanocidal''' contraction of global human-societal self-reproduction that such a reversal entails.

That feeling of estrangement on the part of workers is also, in part, well-founded. It is well-founded, not as an urge to the abstract negation of "technology" as "technology" is shaped and deformed by the imperatives of the "capital-relation" and the power- and profit-pursuing "capital-praxis", but as an urge to the immanent, «aufheben», dialectical negation of that "technology": the creation of a technological social infrastructure fit for use by the "associated producers" [Marx], in their expanded reproduction of an actualized human[e] society, thereby ending human pre-history, and beginning the actual[ized] history of humanity as such.

Within the capital-relation, within the epoch of the real domination of the human [re-]production-process by capital, "technology" develops and accumulates physically as "fixed capital" — as an objectification and materialization of THE CAPITAL-RELATION itself: "technology as capital"; "capital as a technology".

"Fixed capital" develops as an instrument for the subjugation of workers as "variable capital", and with an imperative toward the production of ever escalating and accumulating "pollution", etc., "externalities" against which the "market failures" — the externality-regulation-failing "market-forces" — of the "capital-relation" provide no immanent protection.

This "technology" therefore develops in a manner which is disfigured, deformed, and perverted with respect to the designs of a communist political-ECONOMIC DEMOCRACY, aiming at the production of SOCIAL use-value/SOCIAL negentropy.

Only within an emergent post-capitalist, post-pre-historic, "communist society" — i.e., only within the social relations of society self-re-production of a political-ECONOMIC DEMOCRACY — can the expansion of humanity's self-expansive, self-creative, self-reproductive powers become a conscious project of humanity — a matter of democratic deliberation and of collective-conscious design.

Only then can we ourselves become our works of art.

Only then can humanity become its own work, of art.

Only then will the «kosmos» be our canvas.

Evidence

The following excerpts — from the published writings of Karl Marx, as well as from his surviving writings which he left unpublished at the time of his death — provide evidence as to his resonances with the theses expressed above.

  1. Marx introduces this 'fundamentality' of his critical concept of the human-social "forces of production" in his letter to Pavel Vasilyevich Annenkov, dated 28 December 1846, on the eve of the Europe-wide revolutionary upheaval of 1848:
    "Needless to say, man is not free to choose his productive forces — upon which his whole history is based — for every productive force is an acquired force, the product of previous activity. Thus the productive forces are the result of man's practical energy, but that energy is in turn circumscribed by the conditions in which man is placed by the productive forces already acquired, by the form of society which exists before him, which he does not create, which is the product of the preceding generation. The simple fact that every succeeding generation finds productive forces acquired by the preceding generation and which serve it as the raw material of further production, engenders a relatedness in the history of man, engenders a history of mankind, which is all the more a history of mankind as man's productive forces, and hence his social relations, have expanded. From this it can only be concluded that the social history of man is never anything else than the history of his individual development, whether he is conscious of this or not."

    [Source: Karl Marx & Frederick Engels; Collected Works (Volume 38); International Publishers (New York: 1982); pages 95-106. Quoted in: Paul Paolucci; Marx's Scientific Dialectics; Brill (Boston: 2007); page 79. italics emphasis as in original].
  2. Marx's first published summary of the findings of his '[psycho-]historical materialism', as coupled with the first published systematic rendering of a portion of his [immanent] critique of capitalist political economy, from the Preface to Zur Kritik der politischen Oekonomie, first published in 1859:
    The general conclusion at which I arrived and which, once reached, became the guiding principle of my studies can be summarized as follows. In the social production of their existence, men inevitably enter into definite relations, which are independent of their will, namely relations of production appropriate to a given stage in the development of their material forces of production. The totality of these relations of production constitutes the economic structure of society, the real foundation, on which arises a legal and political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousness. The mode of production of material life conditions the general process of social, political, and intellectual life. It is not the consciousness of men that determines their existence, but their social existence which determines their consciousness. At a certain stage of development, the material productive forces of society come into conflict with the existing relations of production, or — this merely expresses the same thing in legal terms — with the property relations within the framework of which they had operated hitherto. From forms of the development of the productive forces these relations turn into their fetters. Then begins an era of social revolution.

    [Karl Marx; Zur Kritik der politischen Oekonomie; International Publishers; NY: 1970; pages 20-22. Bold, italics, underline, and color emphasis added by anonymous].
    This opposition between the social forces of production and the social relations of production is usually assumed to be a process of the "social unconscious", going on "behind the backs" of the agent social individuals, and never explicitly represented as such privately, or publicly, within the ideological forms of intellectual expression of this social-revolutionary conflict. Our hypothesis, in the section above, broaches the possibility that this conflict, if only in the historical extremity of the final "prehistoric" epoch of human social formation, can become a conscious one, secretly, within the innermost deliberations of the ruling faction of the capital-owning class-for-itself that emerges from the historical development of the capital-relation.

  3. We go to a key writing of Marx, left unpublished in his lifetime, for evidence of the crucial core of the definition of the concept he named "the social forces of production", a core meaning which militates against the feelings of estrangement, for non-capitalists, that tend to associate with this phrase:
    Productive forces and social relationships — the two different sides of the development of the social individual — appear to be, and are, only a means, for capital, to enable it to produce from its own cramped base. But in fact they are the material conditions that will shatter this foundation.

    [David McLellan (editor and translator); The Grundrisse – Karl Marx ; Harper & Row (NY: 1971); page 143. Bold, italics, underline, and color emphasis added by anonymous].
    This passage from the Grundrisse makes clear that, in Marx's thinking, the human-social forces of production exist as a predicate, not only of each human society as a whole — of each historically-specific human social formation — but also, because "the social individual" is a "concrete universal" in Marx's thought, as a predicate of each and every individual human person constituent of that social formation.

    "Productive force", 'society-productive force', the productivity of 'societal self-production', the 'reproductivity' of a human society's self-reproduction, is thus also a 'self-power' of that human individual [within that association] — with respect to nature, including human nature — i.e., in the context of that human society, and of the "self-productivity" of its "collective labor" of continual "production" of itself as a self-evolving whole within also its "other-determination" by the impact upon it of the rest of the universe, the rest of Nature.

    Likewise, per this passage, "social relationships" — i.e., the dominant human-social "relationship" of production in each epoch of human [social] formation — is a predicate of both the developing human society as a whole, and of the developing human person as a social individual; as a constituent thereof.

    The primary historical "human-social relationships of production", or '''forms of human-social intercourse''' [See K. Marx & F. Engels, The German Ideology], listed in the order of their appearance/emergence in human [pre-]history, can be named as follows:

    • Predation — immediate, predatory appropriation of the raw products of pre-human/extra-human nature ["foraging", "scavenging", "hunting and gathering", etc.];

    • Goods/intra-tribal "Gifts", or human-labor-improved[-for-humans] nature-products [e.g., selectively-bred, "domesticated" plants and animals], «aufheben»-subsuming the 'predation-relation';

    • pre-money, barterable Commodities, or "the commodity-relation", «aufheben»-subsuming the 'Goods/Gifts-relation', as well as the relation preceding that relation;

    • pre-capital Money, or "the money-relation", «aufheben»-subsuming "the commodity-relation", as well as the preceding human-social relations of production;

    • Capital, or "the capital-relation", «aufheben»-subsuming "the money relation", as well as the preceding human-social relations of production, e.g., as "money-capital" and as "commodity-capital";

    • "free association", '''the associated property-relation''', or '''the social-property-relationship''', «aufheben»-subsuming "the capital-/wage-labor-relationship", and all other/previous "social relationships of production".

  4. The development of the human-social forces of production is expected to continue, by Marx — and must continue, per Marx — beyond the epoch of 'capital-centered society', into the epoch of "communist society", i.e., the epoch of global 'political-economic democracy'. The human-social forces of production must continue to grow within the epoch of "communist society" as an ineluctable natural condition of human social reproduction, and as an expression of the "human essence":
    We have seen that the capitalist process of production is a historically determined form of the social process of production in general.

    The latter is as much a production process of material conditions of human life as a process taking place under specific historical and economic production relations, producing and reproducing these production relations themselves, and thereby also the bearers of this process, their material conditions of existence and their mutual relations, i.e., their particular socio-economic form.

    For the aggregate of these relations, in which the agents of this production stand with respect to Nature and to one another, and in which they produce, is precisely society, considered from the standpoint of its economic structure.

    Like all its predecessors, the capitalist process of production proceeds under definite material conditions, which are, however, simultaneously the bearers of definite social relations entered into by individuals in the process of reproducing their life.

    Those conditions, like those relations, are on the one hand prerequisites, on the other hand results and creations of the capitalist process of production; they are produced and reproduced by it.

    We saw also that capital — and the capitalist is merely capital personified, and functions in the process of production solely as the agent of capital — in its corresponding process of production, pumps a definite quantity of surplus-labour out of the direct producers, or labourers; capital obtains this surplus-labour without an equivalent, and in essence it always remains forced labour — no matter how much it may seem to result form free contractual agreement. This surplus-labour appears as surplus-value, and this surplus-value exists as a surplus-product.

    Surplus-labour in general, as labour performed over and above the given requirements, must always remain.

    In the capitalist as well as in the slave system, etc., it merely assumes an antagonistic form, and is supplemented by the complete idleness of a stratum of society.

    A definite quantity of surplus-labour is required as insurance against accidents, and by the necessary and progressive expansion of the process of reproduction in keeping with the development of the needs and the growth of population, which is called accumulation from the viewpoint of the capitalist.

    It is one of the civilizing aspects of capital that it enforces this surplus-labour in a manner and under conditions which are more advantageous to the development of the productive forces, social relations, and the creation of the elements for a new and higher form than under the preceding forms of slavery, serfdom, etc.

    Thus it gives rise to a stage, on the one hand, in which coercion and monopolization of social development (including its material and intellectual advantages) by one portion of society at the expense of the other are eliminated; on the other hand, it creates the material means and the embryonic conditions, making it possible for a higher form of society to combine this surplus-labour with a greater reduction of time devoted to material labour in general.

    For, depending on the development of labour productivity, surplus-labour may be large in a small total working-day, and relatively small in a large total working-day.

    If the necessary labour-time = 3 and the surplus-labour = 3, then the total working-day = 6 and the rate of surplus-labour = 100%.

    If the necessary labour = 9 and the surplus-labour = 3, then the total working-day = 12 and the rate of surplus-labour = 33 1/3%.

    In that case, it depends upon the labour productivity how much use-value shall be produced in a definite time, hence also in a definite surplus labour-time.

    The actual wealth of society, and the possibility of constantly expanding its reproduction process, therefore, do not depend upon the duration of surplus-labour, but upon its productivity and the more or less copious conditions of production under which it is performed.

    In fact, the realm of freedom actually begins only where labour which is determined by necessity and mundane considerations ceases; thus, in the very nature of things, it lies beyond the sphere of actual material production,

    Just as the savage must wrestle with Nature to satisfy his wants, to maintain and reproduce life, so must civilized man, and he must do so in all social formations and under all possible modes of production.

    With his development this realm of physical necessity expands as a result of his wants; but, at the same time, the forces of production which satisfy these wants also increase.

    Freedom in this field can only consist is socialized man, the associated producers, rationally regulating their interchange with Nature, bringing it under their common control, instead of being ruled by it as by the blind forces of Nature; and achieving this with the least expenditure of energy and under conditions most favourable to, and worthy of, their human nature.

    But it nonetheless still remains a realm of necessity.

    Beyond it begins that development of human energy which is an end in itself, the true realm of freedom, which, however, can blossom forth only with this realm of necessity as its basis.

    The shortening of the working-day is its basic prerequisite.

    [Karl Marx; Capital (volume III), pages 818-820. Bold, italics, underline, and color emphasis added by anonymous].
  5. That is, the necessity of the development of the human-social forces of production for continued human social reproduction does not end with the end of capitalist society:
    There appears here the universalizing tendency of capital, which distinguishes it from all previous stages of production.

    Although limited by its very nature, it strives towards the universal development of the forces of production, and thus becomes the presupposition of a new mode of production, which is founded not on the development of the forces of production for the purpose of reproducing or at most expanding a given condition, but where the free, unobstructed, progressive, and universal development of the forces of production is itself the presupposition of society and hence of its reproduction. ...

    The barrier to capital is that this entire development proceeds in a contradictory way, and that the working-out of the productive forces, of general wealth, etc., knowledge, etc., appears in such a way that the working individual alienates himself [sich entäussert]; relates to the conditions brought out of him by his labour as those not of his own but of an alien wealth and of his own poverty.

    But this antithetical form is itself fleeting, and produces the real conditions of its own suspension. The result is: the tendentially and potentially general development of the forces of production — of wealth as such — as a basis; likewise, the universality of intercourse, hence the world market as basis.

    The basis as the possibility of the universal development of the individual, and the real development of the individuals from this basis as a constant suspension of its barrier, which is recognized as a barrier, not taken for a sacred limit.

    Not an ideal or imagined universality of the individual, but the universality of his real and ideal relations.

    Hence also the grasping of his own history as a process, and the recognition of nature (equally present as power over nature) as his real body.

    The process of development itself posited and known as the presupposition of the same.

    For this, however, necessary above all that the full development of the forces of production has become the condition of production; and not that specific conditions of production are posited as a limit to the development of the productive forces.

    [Karl Marx; Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy; Martin Nicolaus (translator); Penguin (New York: 1973); pages 540-542. Bold, italics, underline, and color emphasis added by anonymous].
    "Communist society" is, precisely, the society of the uninterrupted development of the human-social forces of self-expanding human-societal self-reproduction, which includes the reproduction of the rest of nature as the real body of humanity.

  6. Neither does the fact, and the necessity, of the development of the human-social forces of production — as inseparable from the continued self-reproduction of human society, and as the core of the Marxian explanation of human-social evolution/revolution — begin with capitalist society:
    This tendency [toward the universal development of the human-social forces of production — anonymous] — which capital possesses, but which at the same time, since capital is a limited form of production, contradicts it and hence drives it towards dissolution — distinguishes capital from all earlier modes of production, and at the same time contains this element, that capital is posited as a mere point of transition.

    All previous forms of society — or, what is the same, of the forces of social production — foundered on the development of wealth.

    Those thinkers of antiquity who were possessed of consciousness therefore directly denounced wealth as the dissolution of the community.

    The feudal system, for its part, foundered on urban industry, trade, modern agriculture (even as a result of individual inventions like gunpowder and the printing press).

    With the development of wealth — and hence also new powers and expanded intercourse on the part of individuals — the economic conditions on which the community rested were dissolved, along with the political relations of the various constituents of the community which corresponded to those conditions: religion, in which it was viewed in idealized form (and both [religion and political relations] rested in turn on a given relation to nature, into which all productive force resolves itself); the character, outlook etc. of individuals.

    The development of science alone — i.e. the most solid form of wealth, both its product and its producer — was sufficient to dissolve these communities.

    But the development of science, this ideal and at the same time practical wealth, is only one aspect, one form in which the development of the human productive forces, i.e., of wealth, appears.

    Considered ideally, the dissolution of a given form of consciousness sufficed to kill a whole epoch.

    In reality, this barrier to consciousness corresponds to a definite degree of development of the forces of material production and hence of wealth.

    True, there was not only a development on the old basis, but also a development of this basis itself.

    The highest development of this basis itself (the flower into which it transforms itself; but it is also this basis, this plant as flower; hence wilting after the flowering and as consequence of the flowering) is the point at which it is itself worked out, developed, into the form in which it is compatible with the highest development of the forces of production, hence also the richest development of the individuals.

    As soon as this point is reached, the further development appears as decay, and the new development begins from a new basis.

    [Karl Marx; Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy; pages 540-541. Bold, italics, underline, and color emphasis added by anonymous].
    More specifically, Marx applies his concept of the development of the human-social forces of human-societal self-re-production to the [meta-]evolution of pre-slavery and pre-serfdom social formations as well, as follows:
    The fundamental condition of property based on tribalism ... is to be a member of the tribe.

    Consequently a tribe conquered and subjugated by another becomes propertyless and part of the inorganic conditions of the conquering tribe's reproduction, which that community regards as its own.

    Slavery and serfdom are therefore simply further developments of property based on tribalism.

    But this also clearly means that these conditions change.

    What makes a region of the earth into a hunting-ground, is being hunted over by tribes; what turns the soil into a prolongation of the body of the individual is agriculture.

    Once the city of Rome had been built and its surrounding land cultivated by its citizens, the conditions of the community were different from what they had been before.

    The object of all of these communities is preservation, i.e. the production of the individuals which constitute them as proprietors, i.e. in the same objective mode of existence, which also forms the relationship of the members to each other, and therefore forms the community itself.

    But this reproduction is at the same time necessarily new production and the destruction of the old form. ...

    The act of reproduction itself changes not only the objective conditions — e.g. transforming village into town, the wilderness into agricultural clearings, etc. — but the producers change with it, by the emergence of new qualities, by transforming and developing themselves in production, forming new powers and new conceptions, new modes of intercourse, new needs, and new speech. ...

    The community itself appears as the first great force of production. ...


    In the last instance the community and the property resting upon it can be reduced to a specific stage in the development of the forces of production of the labouring subjects — to which correspond specific relations of these subjects with each other and with nature.

    Up to a certain point, reproduction. Thereafter, it turns into dissolution. ...

    These forms are of course more or less naturally evolved, but at the same time also the results of a historic process.

    The evolution of the forces of production dissolves them, and their dissolution is itself an evolution of the human forces of production.

    [Karl Marx; Grundrisse: Pre-Capitalist Economic Formations; International Publishers (New York: 1965); pages 92-95. Bold, italics, underline, and color emphasis added by anonymous].

Conclusion

The growth of the human-social "forces of production" is the very '''heart and soul''' of Marxian theory; of its explanation of the causation of human-social evolution, and of human-social revolution, as also of Marx's root definition of the very essence of "communist society".

Those who deny this, are — whatever else they may or may not be — quite simply not Marxians.


Equitism
http://www.equitism.org
theorist@equitism.org